Welcome to my blog!

Every morning, I begin with a cup of coffee and 15 minutes of free thinking. I write down everything that comes to mind, from new ideas to thoughts that emerged overnight. This is where I develop and refine my new research. You'll find some repetition and ideas still in progress. Some might seem unusual or unclear at first, but that's part of the journey! I'm excited to share how my ideas form and evolve.

Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

The Final Reckoning of 'Same Logic, Same Response': Paving the Way for Meta-Coherence

This blog post marks the end of the "same logic, same response" slogan, transitioning towards the nuanced concept of "meta-coherence" in varied decision-making contexts.

The slogan “same logic, same response” did not resonate as I had hoped. Let's revisit the idea. I've been contemplating the concept of “meta-coherence.” While coherence pertains to the logical structures of arguments, beliefs, or theories, meta-coherence transcends this, operating on a higher level. To illustrate, consider two arguments that share logical structures but differ in content. Take, for example, Luxon's argument for repealing the smokefree legislation and its logical applicability to cannabis. Luxon's main point was that restricting distribution boosts crime and creates a black market. This is undoubtedly true for cannabis, where distribution restrictions are absolute, leading to a solely black market presence. Governments, naturally, aim to avoid crime and black markets, especially in drug distribution. The logic underpinning these arguments is identical, though their subjects differ.

Requesting Luxon to exhibit “meta-coherence” is essentially asking him to acknowledge this shared logic. However, this doesn't mean the government's approach to cannabis should mirror its stance on cigarette distribution. This is the point where the “same logic, same response” slogan falters. By “same response,” I didn't imply identical actions but rather a uniform attitude toward the logic of the argument, a testament to “meta-coherence.” In non-deductive decision-making contexts, external factors beyond the premises' scope influence the final decision. Cigarettes have a big health toll on society, are addictive, cause cancer, cost a lot of money, and are ultimately something bad for society (right?). Cannabis, as a recreational drug, has effects on society and individuals that are much less than those of other legal drugs such as alcohol, and indeed cigarettes (right?).

Luxon's stance on cannabis seems to favor the status quo, overlooking the stronger argument for legalizing recreational cannabis, which his logic inadvertently supports. This inconsistency ignores that the context might actually favor legal cannabis distribution while maintaining smokefree legislation. My initial “same response” advocacy has evolved into a deeper understanding. I champion a uniform recognition of logical coherence across various contexts. Logic is a critical component in decision-making but doesn't dictate the best course of action. It ensures coherence before considering external factors and context-specific details. "Meta-coherence," as I term it, entails evaluating argument coherence consistently – the 'meta' aspect. While “meta-coherence” might sound contrived, it captures my intention better than “same logic, same response”... To be continued.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Reevaluating the Slogan: The Pitfalls of 'Same Logic, Same Response’

I examine the 'same logic, same response' slogan, focusing on its limitations.

It’s time we reconsider the slogan “same logic, same response”. Currently, it struggles to effectively communicate what I aim to express. When taken literally, albeit with necessary qualifications, the slogan is misleading. I fear an overreliance on numerous caveats might lead to ad hoc justifications, which is not ideal. Let's delve into this.

The statement is inaccurate when interpreted literally, as logic alone doesn’t encapsulate the entirety of an argument's quality. An argument can be logical yet still flawed due to its false premises. Consider a frivolous example: "All logicians are unicorns. Patrick is a logician. Therefore, Patrick is a unicorn." This represents a valid argument, hence logically impeccable, but it's fundamentally flawed because the premise is untrue – no logician is a unicorn. Another argument with identical logical structure might be sound if its premises are true. For instance, “All humans are mortal. Patrick is a human. Therefore, Patrick is mortal.” Although these two arguments share the same logical framework, I don’t anticipate an identical response to both. I hope to have not convinced you of my mythical status, but I can assure you, I am indeed mortal.

So, the first caveat: by "the same response", I refer to an identical logical evaluation. This means assessing whether the premises logically support the conclusion. Both cited examples are valid, and thus, from a logician’s perspective, they are equally logical. This pertains specifically to deductive reasoning, where the standards are centered around validity.

In non-deductive scenarios, additional caveats are required, as context influences logical support. Non-deductive contexts are marked by more flexible logical standards, focusing on argument strength rather than validity. The premises here do not fully guarantee the conclusion, allowing a margin for error, which varies according to the context. Take this example: "90% of Aucklanders are zombies. Patrick is an Aucklander. Therefore, Patrick is a zombie." What are the odds of Patrick being a zombie based solely on the given premises? 90%, seemingly. It’s a probable hypothesis, though not certain. However, if new information emerges – say, no zombies have yet reached Waiheke Island, and Patrick resides there – the likelihood of Patrick being a zombie drops significantly.

This leads to the need for another caveat in non-deductive contexts. My colleague proposed incorporating a 'ceteris paribus' clause, modifying the slogan to “same logic, same response, all else being equal.” What exactly needs to remain constant? As I’ve elaborated in "Logic in the Wild", this is a complex issue, which I invite you to explore further in the book for a comprehensive understanding of 'ceteris paribus logic'.

For the purposes of this post, we can simplify it to mean that the information surrounding the premises should remain equal. If the only information available is that within the premises, with no external data, we attain a greater degree of logical stability across various contexts, including in non-deductive reasoning.

An application of this principle can be seen in political discourse. For instance, when critiquing the Prime Minister's lack of what I term 'meta-coherence' (a concept for another post) in handling cigarettes and cannabis policies, this principle comes into play. If the rationale for not reducing cigarette sale outlets is to avoid a black market, a similar logical approach should apply to cannabis, ceteris paribus. However, as expected, counterarguments often highlight dissimilarities in context, as exemplified by Luxon's “different story, different effects” response.

Hence, the second caveat: the context of evaluation must remain equal. Of course, one might argue, as Luxon did, that the contexts are not equal. This illustrates the need for further caveats, potentially leading to an unwieldy number of ad hoc qualifications for the "same logic, same response" slogan.

I'll leave the discussion here for now, intending to revisit and potentially reformulate this slogan in a future post. There’s much more to unpack, but for now, I must attend to other matters.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Seeking logical coherence in political discourse

Prime Minister Christopher Luxon’s approach to New Zealand's smokefree legislation and cannabis policies reveals a fluctuating application of logic, highlighting challenges in maintaining logical coherence in political discourse.

Prime Minister Christopher Luxon of New Zealand recently faced challenges regarding his party’s decision to repeal the smokefree legislation. This controversy stemmed from his claim that limiting cigarette sales to a single store in Northland would escalate crime and foster a black market. However, journalists highlighted inaccuracies in Luxon's assertion, noting that there would actually be 18 stores, not just one.

In response, during a press conference, Luxon attempted to clarify, suggesting he misspoke. He argued that the proposed policy would only allow a few stores to sell cigarettes across large regions, which would attract crime to these outlets and promote a black market. Luxon transformed his response into a logical point, stating: “[It] doesn't change a thing. The bigger point still holds that actually the reason why we opposed the legislation at the time is - and remember it hasn't taken effect, it's come into law but it hasn't taken effect - was simply to say we think that's the wrong way to go about it. […] Limiting distribution in that way, concentrating it in a few retail outlets, makes those stores a real magnet for crime, particularly in small towns up and down New Zealand - and importantly will drive into a black market." He suggests that the crux of the matter lies not in the exact number of stores, but in the scarcity of them, which could lead to concentrated crime and a black market.

This point holds a logical coherence: whether it is one or 18 stores in large regions, the essential fear is the limited number of outlets, potentially sufficient for the anticipated negative outcomes. While not strictly valid in a logicians' sense, this argument is logically strong or could be further strengthened with additional reasoning.

In a blog post last week, we discussed an instance where Luxon was presented with a logical point by Ryan Bridge, specifically that the logic Luxon applied to tobacco could similarly be applied to cannabis in terms of legal considerations and distribution. Luxon's response was to dismiss this as a 'different story'. In doing so, he seemed to overlook the logical point and instead focused on the specifics of the argument. This approach implies a misconception that altering the content of an argument can destroy its logical foundation. One of the key strengths of logical reasoning in decision-making is its invariance to changes in content.

One week later, Luxon reiterated his stance by acknowledging errors in his initial facts but maintained that the foundational reasoning remained unchanged: limited distribution leads to increased crime and a black market. This principle, as Bridge highlighted, applies as much to cannabis as it does to cigarettes. The existence of a black market for cannabis is solely due to the absence of legal distribution channels. The principle of applying the same logical framework, regardless of the subject matter ("same logic, same response"), is evident here. However, Luxon's varying approaches in different contexts raise concerns. His application of logic seems to fluctuate, mirroring a student who understands enough to apply logic in specific scenarios but not uniformly across different contexts. Such a hesitant approach to applying logical principles, especially by a government in alliance with a demagogical party, is troubling. It suggests an inconsistency in the application of logical analysis in policy-making, which is concerning for anyone with an understanding of logic."

References: https://www.newshub.co.nz/home/politics/2023/12/smokefree-laws-prime-minister-christopher-luxon-admits-blunder-on-tobacco-store-numbers.html

https://www.newshub.co.nz/home/politics/2023/11/election-2023-incoming-pm-christopher-luxon-defends-removing-smokefree-legislation-hits-out-labour-s-policies.html

Post-Blog Edit:

Luxon doubled down on his position during an interview on the morning show today, offering statements that align even more closely with the themes of this blog: “I just think it's pretty difficult to sort of manage going forward, but the major reason is that limiting distribution creates a black market and ultimately will create more crime." These comments provide a clearer insight into his reasoning and further underscore the points discussed in our blog regarding logical coherence in political discourse.

Reference: https://www.newshub.co.nz/home/politics/2023/12/smokefree-laws-luxon-admits-he-doesn-t-know-how-many-lives-could-be-lost-by-scrapping-regulations.html

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Same Logic, Same Response - testing the Slogan's Robustness in New Zealand's Policy Debates

This post delves into the contrasting responses of New Zealand's Prime Minister Christopher Luxon to cannabis and tobacco policies, offering the opportunity to test the robustness of the “same logic, same response” slogan.

The slogan "same logic, same response" often encounters challenges in the realm of political decision-making, as evidenced by the actions of politicians who, regardless of their stated intentions, can diverge from logical pathways for various reasons, including economic or power gains. This brings to mind a recent political developments in New Zealand.

Christopher Luxon has recently ascended to the role of Prime Minister, alongside a coalition of conservative and demagogical parties. A significant early move of this new administration is the proposed repeal of the smokefree legislation. This legislation, a pioneering effort by the previous government, aimed to eradicate tobacco accessibility for individuals born from 2009 onwards.

A pivotal moment occurred during Luxon's first appearance as Prime Minister on a morning show, hosted by Ryan Bridge. The exchange highlighted a key point of contention:

“Luxon: The changes that the government were making we think have some unintended consequences that aren't actually helpful... When you've actually limited distribution and you're the only place selling smokes in some towns in New Zealand, you become a massive target for crime and for ram raids, and there will be an expanded black market that will be largely untaxed.

Bridge: Couldn't you make the same argument for cannabis? I mean, you're talking about not wanting to have a black market, wanting to be able to tax the externality. Why don't you do a similar thing with cannabis?

Luxon: Yeah, different story, different effects, but I mean the reality here is we've got a tool in vapes which has actually helped a lot of people coming off smokes, which has been good. Now I've got to make sure that we protect young people in particular in their access to vaping, and that's important we have tougher consequences there. We'll continue to drive smoking down as successive governments have done, through good education.”

In this dialogue, Luxon's response, "different story, different effects," shifts the focus from the logical comparison to the unique narratives surrounding tobacco and cannabis. The historical legality of tobacco, its societal acceptance compared to the moral stigmatisation of cannabis, and the public debates, particularly during New Zealand's cannabis legalisation referendum, all paint distinct "stories" for each substance.

However, Bridge's argument wasn't about the individual narratives of these substances. Instead, it was about the shared logic underpinning the market dynamics of both: liberalisation potentially reduces black markets and increases tax revenues. This was Luxon's original argument for tobacco, which Bridge contends applies equally to cannabis, hence the "same logic, same response" stance.

I'll have to revisit the slogan's robustness in future posts. Luxon might be right in asserting distinct narratives for cannabis and tobacco, possibly disrupting the uniform application of logic. For logicians, this presents a challenge in non-deductive reasoning, especially when context alters the impact of counterarguments. This exploration might reveal the limitations of the "same logic, same response" principle in complex policy scenarios.

Reference: https://www.newshub.co.nz/home/politics/2023/11/election-2023-incoming-pm-christopher-luxon-defends-removing-smokefree-legislation-hits-out-labour-s-policies.html

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Same Logic, Same Response: Unpacking Key's Apollo 13 and COVID-19 Analogy

I further dissect John Key's flawed analogy of New Zealand's COVID response with Apollo 13, emphasizing the 'same logic, same response' principle

Upon revisiting John Key's analogy between New Zealand's COVID-19 response and NASA's handling of the Apollo 13 mission, I've developed a more nuanced appreciation of his critique. Key points out that the New Zealand government lacked the proactive problem-solving demonstrated by NASA. He admires NASA's adeptness in responding to unforeseen challenges, suggesting that New Zealand should have emulated this approach.

Yet, Key's comparison fails to fully grasp the parallel nature of the situations. Both NASA during the Apollo 13 crisis and the New Zealand government faced sudden, unanticipated emergencies. In both instances, the need was to devise immediate, practical solutions within the unique constraints of each scenario. The New Zealand government’s strategy, much like NASA’s, involved navigating a precarious and unpredictable situation with the available resources and knowledge.

Further analysis of Key's argument reveals a somewhat impractical suggestion. It is comparable to advising NASA to send a new shuttle to the endangered Apollo 13 astronauts – a proposal that isn't fit for purpose. This aspect of his analogy seems to overlook the crucial need for responding to similar scenarios similarly. Such an approach is a key element in effectively managing both the Apollo 13 and COVID-19 scenarios.

This discussion guides us towards the broader logical concept of meta-coherence, an idea I am continuing to refine. Meta-coherence involves identifying a shared logical structure across different scenarios and responding in a manner that respects this coherence. At the heart of this concept is the principle of 'same logic, same response.' This principle suggests that when two distinct situations, such as the Apollo 13 mission and the COVID-19 pandemic, exhibit similar logical patterns – particularly in their need for swift and feasible responses – our approach should mirror this shared logical underpinning. This leads to similar responses in seemingly different contexts that share coherence.

Through this lens, Key's analogy emerges as meta-incoherent. While he rightly notes the skillful problem-solving in the Apollo 13 mission, he does not appropriately transpose this logical understanding to New Zealand's handling of the pandemic. His expectations for the government's actions did not reflect the 'same logic, same response' principle, which advocates for a logical and situation-aware evaluation across different scenarios.

While Key's analogy initially appears to offer an inspiring analogy, its success diminishes under the scrutiny of meta-coherence.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Meta-Coherence in Logic: From Halloween Candy to Apollo 13's Mailbox

I explore the concept of meta-coherence in logic, drawing parallels between a Halloween candy conundrum and the Apollo 13 mission, and critiquing John Key's meta-incoherent use of this analogy.

In "Logic in the Wild," I delve into the intriguing ways logic seamlessly integrates into various aspects of life, linking arguments that, at first glance, appear vastly different. The distinction lies not in the logical structure, but in the content. For instance, consider the scenario of two twins trick-or-treating: one twin's costume is intact, while the other's is accidentally torn. A mean logician gives the twin with the intact costume ten candies, but only one to the other. The children protest, arguing that an accidental tear shouldn’t result in such unequal treatment. In response, the logician retracts nine candies from the first twin, addressing the inequality in a logically coherent, yet seemingly unfair manner.

This situation mirrors arguments like the defence for cannabis legalisation, which often compares its tarnished reputation to that of alcohol, arguing for equal legal treatment. Following the logician’s approach, one could argue to make alcohol illegal, thereby eliminating the perceived disparity. Both scenarios highlight an essential logical principle: coherence does not always equate to desirable outcomes.

Furthering this exploration, I propose another perspective of logic as a guardian of 'meta-coherence'. Reflecting on an incident during the COVID-19 pandemic, former New Zealand Prime Minister John Key criticised the government’s haphazard health measures, drawing an analogy to the Apollo 13 mission. He suggested that if the New Zealand government had mirrored NASA's problem-solving approach, the populace would have endured less hardship from lockdowns. However, this comparison is meta-incoherently flawed.

The New Zealand government, like NASA, was forced to devise ad hoc solutions to unprecedented challenges, prioritising immediate survival over long-term strategies. Just as NASA's ingenious 'mailbox' solution on Apollo 13 – a makeshift contraption for air filtration made from available materials which you might have spotted in Logic in the Wild's book cover – was a temporary fix, so were the government's measures. These solutions, though not ideal for long-term application, were effective in their respective emergencies.

In my book, "Logic in the Wild," I use Apollo 13 as an illustration of scientific ingenuity in crisis. However, it’s crucial to understand that such makeshift solutions, while lifesaving, are not the blueprint for future standards. This meta-coherent view recognises the similarities in both the Apollo mission and New Zealand's pandemic response: immediate, life-saving solutions, not permanent models of scientific excellence.

Post-Publication Update: Additional Context on John Key's COVID-19 Article

In my earlier discussion, I referenced an essay by former Prime Minister of New Zealand, Sir John Key, wherein he critiqued the government's response to the COVID-19 pandemic. I've since located the specific article I was referring to, published in 2021 by the New Zealand Herald. For those interested in delving deeper and forming their own judgments on the matter, I encourage you to read Sir John Key's perspective. The article, titled 'Covid-19 Delta outbreak: Sir John Key – 5 ideas to transform our approach', can be found at this link: https://www.nzherald.co.nz/nz/covid-19-delta-outbreak-sir-john-key-5-ideas-to-transform-our-approach/PJH3TEOR6WEVADOOHWLKFBVK74/.

In my analysis, I discuss the meta-coherence, or lack thereof, in Key's analogy between the government's pandemic response and the Apollo 13 mission. I invite readers to consider both my arguments and Key's original article. This will provide a broader context and perhaps challenge or reinforce your views on the logical underpinnings of such analogies and their implications in real-world decision-making.

Just a reminder: this blog is a space for raw, evolving thoughts, born from my morning brainstorming sessions over coffee. What you read here is part of an ongoing journey of idea formation and exploration.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Describing the Ideal: The Normative and Descriptive Facets of Logic

Logic is both descriptive and normative, because it describes the ideal.

Is logic normative or descriptive? This question frequently arises in discussions about logic, presenting a challenging dichotomy. However, I find myself unable to firmly choose one over the other. Thus, I often respond, "Yes, it is both normative and descriptive," a typical logician’s answer to a binary question where the option for "both" exists.

First, let's unpack what this question entails. If logic is normative, it functions as a directive force, guiding your thought process, decision-making, and inferential reasoning. A normative theory offers guidance and direction. On the other hand, if logic is descriptive, it assumes the role of an observer, merely documenting the processes of thought, akin to a scientific endeavor aimed at describing and explaining phenomena in the world.

Given this distinction, is logic normative or descriptive? The answer is not straightforward. Logic primarily deals with structure rather than content. It does not dictate how to think or make decisions for you. A common misconception is that logic serves as a rigid, emotionless guide to decision-making, a trope frequently misrepresented in creative media. The character of Spock from Star Trek epitomizes this view, portraying a being governed by the 'laws' of logic, leading to decisions that are seemingly devoid of emotion. However, this is a misrepresentation. Logic, in its essence, is not normative in this regard; it's about coherence rather than content.

Where logic can be considered normative is in its ability to determine which line of reasoning is coherent and which is not, hence my saying, "logic is the guardian of coherence." However, coherence alone is not a direct path to truth. It is possible to construct coherent arguments that lead to completely opposing conclusions. This observation shifts the perspective towards a descriptive understanding of logic. We examine reasoning to determine its coherence, not necessarily its truth or applicability.

Yet, describing logic as purely descriptive, akin to a scientist observing and predicting human thought patterns, also falls short. Human reasoning is complex, often illogical, riddled with biases, emotions, and inconsistencies. Logic is not a naturally occurring phenomenon to be observed.

So, where does this leave us in the normative versus descriptive debate? The dichotomy itself seems to be a false dilemma. It implies a necessity to choose one perspective over the other, yet neither fully encapsulates the essence of logic. That's why I advocate for a synthesis of both views: logic is both normative and descriptive.

To articulate this fusion, I use the phrase “logic is the description of the ideal.” Logicians don't merely describe how people think, akin to psychologists, but rather they model how ideal agents would reason, similar to how economists conceptualize the actions of ideal agents in hypothetical markets. This involves certain assumptions about what constitutes an ideal reasoner. Part of my work, particularly in 'Logic in the Wild,' focuses on reconciling these idealized concepts with real-world reasoning.

Studying these ideal situations is akin to how scientists construct mathematical models: they describe laws operating under controlled, ideal conditions. Therefore, describing the ideal becomes normative, setting a benchmark for evaluating real reasoning. By comparing actual reasoning to this ideal standard, logic begins to guide and inform our thought processes.

In conclusion, logic straddles the line between being normative and descriptive. It is normative because it outlines ideal reasoning, yet it is also descriptive as it explores the structures and patterns of thought. Embracing this duality offers a more comprehensive understanding of logic, moving beyond the confines of choosing one aspect over the other. Logic, in essence, is normative because it describes the ideal.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Understanding Logical Injustice in Daily Life

Exploring logical injustice, the post emphasizes the importance of using appropriate logical standards in everyday discussions and decision-making.

Logical injustice occurs when someone is unfairly hindered from recognizing the coherence in their thoughts and expressions. This may stem from the imposition of inappropriate logical standards in situations where they don't apply. A classic example of this is responding with the strict standards of mathematical validity during a casual family reunion dinner—a party trick I've learned to ditch, albeit perhaps a few awkward family gatherings too late. Let’s explore this further.

Imagine a scenario where someone is wrestling with a significant life decision, such as relocating to a different city for a new job opportunity. This choice is fraught with uncertainty and will undoubtedly affect their entire family. In such a situation, relying solely on logical validity as a guiding principle can be more obstructive than helpful.

For instance, any argument they make in favour of moving can be countered with extreme or highly improbable scenarios. Consider the possibility of better career prospects and personal growth in the new city. A counter-argument might point out the instability of the world, suggesting the potential bankruptcy of the new company and the consequent isolation in an unfamiliar city. Or, to take it to an absurd level, one might argue about the unlikely event of extraterrestrial abduction at the new job, rendering any decision moot.

Although these counter-arguments technically make sense because they offer counterexamples, they aren't really useful or relevant in practice. In situations like these, sticking rigidly to logical validity doesn't help. It stops the person from sharing a clear and sensible argument for why moving could be beneficial. Basically, this is a case of logical injustice, where the right reasoning is overshadowed by overly strict logic.

To effectively handle these situations, it's essential to identify which logical approaches are suitable for each conversation. Striking a balance between clear reasoning and real-world applicability is crucial for encouraging meaningful and constructive discussions, particularly when it comes to personal and emotionally significant decisions.

Being logically just is not just about being logically correct; it's about understanding the context and applying logical principles that are fitting and constructive. By doing so, we not only respect others' viewpoints but also contribute to more coherent and considerate decision-making processes.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Embracing Understanding: The Art of Logical Charity in Conversations

Drawing from the traditional principle of charity, I introduce the Principle of Logical Charity, encouraging the treatment of others' views as both intelligent and logically coherent in conversations.

The principle of charity asks us to view others as intelligent beings. It's tempting to highlight errors in someone's beliefs to discredit them. Yet, this approach can lead to misunderstandings and missed opportunities for rich dialogue. Imagine Ash argues that our capability to land on Mars signals that we could redirect our scientific focus to solve major issues like world hunger, rather than enhancing cell phone technology. If I simply dismiss Ash's point by pointing out the factual inaccuracy - we haven't landed on Mars - it's an uncharitable response. Ash probably knows it was the Moon, not Mars, and their error was more of a science fiction Freudian slip. The principle of charity would lead us to gently correct this slip-up and engage more deeply with Ash's underlying argument.

Alongside this, there's the idea I call the Principle of Logical Charity. It challenges us to see others as coherent thinkers. We all deal with a wealth of beliefs and information, trying to make sense of a complex world. This principle is about assuming people are doing their best to express coherent thoughts. Take, for example, the seeming contradictions in Christianity's monotheistic belief system, distinguishing between Jesus and the Holy Spirit, both considered God. Labeling this as incoherent misses the mark. The Principle of Logical Charity would have us find a coherent explanation, such as the concept of 'God being multiply realisable'. This approach doesn't necessarily confirm all aspects of Christian beliefs, but it allows us to understand certain parts coherently. Overlooking this principle can lead to 'logical injustice', where we fail to appreciate the potential coherence in others' views.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

The Dance of Opposition: Bridging Competition and Cooperation

This piece delves into the nuanced spectrum between competition and cooperation, questioning traditional views of these concepts and exploring their roles in both natural and human-made systems.

What really sits at the opposite end of competition? It's tempting to say cooperation, right? But here's a twist: cooperation needs a bit of elbow grease – agency, communication, and coordination. None of these are must-haves for competition’s opposite. Think about it: does competition always need a director? Not really. Picture genes vying for dominance, à la "The Selfish Gene". No need for a mastermind there. Or consider market dynamics. They might boil down to human actions, but it’s not a strict requirement. Take a forest, for instance. It’s like a battleground, where each tree and plant jostles for sunlight and nutrients. But does this struggle hinge on the trees being conscious agents? That’s a hot topic when we talk about plant identity and individuality.

Now, back to cooperation. It screams agency, doesn’t it? But let’s slice the term a bit. Think of it as co-operation: multiple actions interweaving simultaneously. This leans more towards coordination, or maybe just things occurring side by side. Viewing a forest through this lens shifts the perspective. Instead of a scramble for resources, we see a networked community, each member contributing to a collective thrive-fest.

So, what’s the broader picture here? It’s a spectrum ranging from stark individualism to all-encompassing unity. On one end, you've got the extreme breakup – down to atoms, maybe – each doing its own thing. Complex systems, like life or the universe, might emerge from these solo acts. The other end? Total integration. Picture a world where everything’s interconnected, maybe to the point of losing individual identities. Everything's part of a greater whole, a single unit.

Integration's a slippery term, though. It can spring from competition too – think of one country swallowing another post-war. But are there other spectrums to consider? Strip away the rivalry from competition, and you're left with independent happenings. Remove agency from cooperation, and you land at a relational web where everything relies on everything else. It seems we're circling back to the same spectrum after all.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

The Forest as Metaphor: Competing and Cooperating in Nature

In this post, I explore the forest as a metaphor for competition and cooperation, contrasting the individualistic struggle for resources with the collaborative symbiosis of the ecosystem, and introducing relational ontology as a holistic view that transcends these dualities.

Forests embody two distinct viewpoints: competitive and cooperative. In the competitive view, trees battle for sunlight, with the tallest ones overshadowing and outcompeting their neighbours for this vital resource. Lower layers adapt to this scarcity, each straining to capture what little light filters through. This perspective mirrors the cutthroat dynamics of market competition and Darwinian evolution, casting the forest as an arena of individualistic struggle.

In contrast, the cooperative approach sees the forest as a symphony of mutual support. Here, tall trees collaborate to form a protective canopy, shielding the undergrowth from harsh elements like rain and wind, while moderating extreme temperatures. This cooperative nature becomes tangible in the cool refuge forests provide on hot days.

However, this duality sets the stage for a third perspective, drawn from indigenous philosophy: relational ontology. This approach doesn't start with isolated entities in competition or collaboration. Instead, it views the forest as an integrated system, where the distinction between individual trees blurs. Interconnected by their roots, often across species, these trees form a network where life persists even beyond death. This interconnectivity challenges the competitive narrative, revealing the forest not as a collection of solitary fighters but as a cohesive, interconnected community.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Beyond the Self: Exploring Relational Identity and Holistic Connections

This blog delves into the concept of relational identity, drawing from Māori philosophy and Anne Salmond's work, to explore how identity extends beyond personal confines and encompasses a holistic network of relationships, particularly within the LGBTQ+ community.

My exploration into caring about one's identity beyond the private sphere, under the theme of relational identity, stems from a quest to understand the concept itself. This journey began with Anne Salmond's 'Tears of Rangi,' particularly her intriguing assertion that God is an analytic logician. To paraphrase Salmond's ideas, Māori philosophy presents a holistic, relational view of existence. It posits that concepts exist in tandem with their opposites, such that invoking one inherently activates its counterpart. This approach challenges the Cartesian notion of an individual as a distinct entity, separated from the world by the mere boundaries of their skin.

Drawing from the spiralling imagery of the koru, Māori philosophy suggests that identity is influenced by both past and future elements. It encompasses not just our bloodline ancestors but also spiritual entities and geographical features. Identity, in this view, is an integral part of a comprehensive, relational network.

This perspective is particularly enlightening when considering identity in the context of the LGBTQ+ community. The act of 'coming out' transcends mere declarations of sexual orientation or preference. It signifies the establishment of a position within a complex web of relationships. It encompasses the historical struggles and societal challenges faced by rainbow communities, including acts of violence and societal exclusion. But it also involves the relationships one forms and the recognition — legal, societal, and communal — of these relationships. This holistic understanding of queer identity goes far beyond mere sexual practices in the private sphere. To do so would be to overlook the full, interconnected narrative of one's life.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

I don’t care vs I care not

Does "I don’t care what you do in your bedrooms" suggest tolerance or a desire for ignorance? This phrase highlights the unique challenges queer individuals face in expressing their true identities within societal norms.

The phrase “I don’t care what you do in your bedrooms” often raises the question: does it signify tolerance as in “I’m okay with whatever you do in your bedroom,” or does it imply a desire for ignorance, “I care not to know what you do in your bedroom”? This interpretation suggests a boundary where personal activities are accepted as long as they remain unshared and private. This stance advocates for the discretion of one’s private affairs, especially those of a sexual nature, deeming it socially inappropriate to publicize intimate details.

The concept operates smoothly for those whose identities align with societal norms. Heterosexual individuals, for instance, are not compelled to announce their sexual orientation, as their behaviors and appearances typically do not challenge the status quo. Thus, for them, Trudeau's slogan may simply underscore the principle of maintaining sexual privacy. However, this perspective overlooks a crucial distinction for queer individuals: revealing one’s queer identity is not an overshare of sexual life but an integral part of their lived experience.

In societal interactions, such as attending social events with partners, queer individuals inadvertently disclose aspects of their private lives that heterosexual individuals do not. This difference highlights that a queer life is not merely a 'normal' life with an alternate sexual preference; it is an existence that encompasses every facet of being. Therefore, coming out is not about revealing bedroom activities, but rather about sharing one's true self and the entirety of one's life experiences.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

I don’t care what you do in your bedroom

Pierre-Eliot Trudeau's 1970s stance on government non-interference in private matters empowered the queer community, leading to significant progress in rights and recognition, though modern attitudes like "I don't care what you do in your bedroom" still present challenges in fully acknowledging and respecting queer identities.

14/11/23

Pierre-Eliot Trudeau, the former Canadian Prime Minister, was a pivotal figure in the 1970s for decriminalising homosexuality. He famously stated that the government should not meddle in the nation's bedrooms, implying that what consenting adults do in private is not a matter for governmental scrutiny. This forward-thinking attitude was especially empowering for the queer community, enabling them to forge a significant existence within their community. Once their sexuality was decriminalised, they began addressing discrimination in workplaces, eventually leading to the achievement of marriage equality in the 2000s.

A recent example of this ongoing dialogue is Felix Auger-Aliassime, a prominent Canadian tennis player, who suggested a voluntary survey on the pro tour to anonymously identify members of the rainbow community. Notably, there are no openly gay male players on the tour. While several celebrated female players have come out, significantly influencing the community, the number of openly gay players remains minimal.

Reacting to Auger-Aliassime's announcement on Facebook, some echoed a modern variant of Trudeau's sentiment: "I don't care what you do in your bedroom, I only care about how well you play tennis." This attitude, akin to a contemporary "don't ask, don't tell" policy, seems accepting but actually limits the expression and recognition of diverse queer identities. It reduces the act of coming out to a mere declaration of sexual preference, ignoring the broader implications of being queer. Queer identity involves more than just sexuality; it's about how individuals present themselves, form relationships, and contribute to their communities.

From a relational identity viewpoint, the "I don’t care what you do in your bedroom" stance falls short. It overlooks the importance of openly living and expressing a range of queer identities, and the need for acceptance and respect in doing so.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

logic and possible worlds

In this blog post, I explore how my journey as a logician, initially focused on abstract content, evolved to embrace real-world interactions, from teaching diverse students to considering feminist critiques and the nature of metaphysics and mathematics.

13/11/23

Logic focuses on abstract content rather than the structure of the real world, allowing logicians to disengage from worldly matters. Historically, twentieth-century logicians were primarily engaged in establishing consistent foundations for mathematics, which, in many cases, is their most significant interaction with real-world concepts. My own immersion into the 'real world' primarily began with the writing of 'Logic in the Wild' and my collaboration with Tim Dare, teaching a course on Logical and Critical Thinking to a diverse international group of students.

My re-engagement with the real world involved understanding feminist critiques of critical thinking. These critiques emphasize the presence and experiences of people in the world, highlighting how rigid, mathematical approaches to thinking can be oppressive in situations that don't warrant such strict methodologies.

In philosophy, metaphysics deals directly with worldly concepts. It differs from physics, which seeks to uncover and understand the physical laws governing our world, enabling prediction and control. Metaphysics, however, asks broader questions: What are the potential states of the world? Are certain features of the world necessary? For instance, physical laws operate under specific conditions, but they could potentially be different. How might physics look in a world where, say, gravity is stronger or the speed of light varies (can it?)?

These inquiries lead to reflections on the nature of mathematics. Are mathematical laws inherently necessary, or could they be different? What about the existence of necessary entities, like God, does it exist by necessity? Such questions guide logicians to explore the concept of possible worlds. Unlike scientists, who focus on making predictions about our world, logicians adopt a broader perspective, contemplating all the ways the world could potentially be. The primary criterion for considering a world in this context is consistency. Thus, logicians explore a multitude (infinitely many!) of possible worlds, accepting any that are internally consistent. This exploration of possible worlds represents the closest that logicians typically come to engaging with the concept of 'the world'.

Read More
Logical Injustice Patrick Girard Logical Injustice Patrick Girard

Logic and the world

Does logic care about the world?

Logic remains indifferent to the world's specifics. Professional logicians often describe logic as absolute and universal, signifying its principles apply regardless of content or context. In my book, "Logic in the Wild," I characterise logic as the guardian of coherence, focusing on the structure of beliefs (or theories, etc.), rather than their subject matter. It's crucial to distinguish logic from truth: logic is not equipped to discern whether the world harbours giant flying pigs or exists as a computer simulation. By this, I don't imply logic is irrelevant to reality, but rather that it's not a tool for determining factual truths about the world.

Some logicians and mathematicians subscribe to the notion that logic, perhaps akin to mathematics or in its exploration of mathematical concepts, belongs to a Platonic realm. This realm, a domain of ideas or abstract entities like numbers, is considered as tangible as the physical world. If logic were to hold any knowledge about reality, it would pertain to this Platonic realm. This view was espoused by eminent 20th-century logician Kurt Gödel and has influenced thinkers like Roger Penrose, who posits that humans, unlike computers, have direct access to this Platonic part of the world. However, even if we accept that logic (and humans) may interact with a Platonic realm of ideas, logic still remains detached from our physical world.

Interestingly, logic's engagement with the world didn't begin by limiting itself to observable truths. Logicians expanded their purview to include the study of worlds through analyses of possibility and necessity. This aligns with the pursuit of universal truths, but in this context, the universality pertains to necessity. Questions like, "Is it necessary that two plus two equals four?" or "Is it necessary that all humans mortal?" and "Is the existence of giant flying pigs possible?" mark a shift in logic's focus from pure mathematics to an exploration of metaphysical possibilities.

Read More